Historical method.
The how of historical inquiry.
On this page I gather an assortment of quotations from historians
writing about the very business of history, the historical method.
Refer also to my page on the argument
from silence.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 141:
Although work like [Thomas] Carlyle's [On Heroes, Hero-Worship
and the Heroic in History] is surely naive, it is also a mistake to
underestimate the effect an individual can have. Imagine what today's world
would be like had Mohammed, Confucius, or Christ not lived, if Marx had
not written, if there had been no Hitler!
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, pages 43-44:
In order for a source to be used as evidence in a historical
argument, certain basic matters about its form and content must be settled.
First, it must be (or must be made) comprehensible at the most basic level
of language, handwriting, and vocabulary. ....
Second, the source must be carefully located in place and time: when was
it composed, where, in what country or city, in what social setting, by which
individual? Are these apparent "facts" of composition correct?—that is,
is the date indicated, let us say, in a letter written from the front by Dwight
Eisenhower to his wife Mamie the date it was actually written? Is the place
indicated within the source the actual place of composition? If the document
does not itself provide such evidence—or if there is any reason to doubt
the ostensible evidence—is there internal evidence that can be used to
determine a probable date, or a time period within which the document was
created? Can we tell from the content of the document itself or its relationship
to other similar documents where it was composed?
Third, the source must be checked for authenticity. Is it what it purports
to be, let us say an agreement for the transfer of land from a secular lord to
the church or—to mention one of the famous cases of forgery from recent
history—the personal diary of Adolph Hitler? Can we tell from the
handwriting, the rhetoric, anachronisms of content, from the ink or the
watermark or the quality of the parchment—or from the typeface or the
electronic coding of the tape—that the document was not composed where
it presents itself as having been composed? Is it, perhaps, a forgery from
the period, a forgery from a later period, or simply a case of mislabeling
by archivists?
At this point Howell and Prevenier list the principal tools that historians
use in order to authenticate the sources:
- Paleography, the study of handwriting (pages 44-46).
- Diplomatics, the study of charters (page 46).
- Archaeology, the study of artifacts (pages 46-50).
- Statistics, the study of numerical data (pages 50-55).
- Miscellaneous tools (page 56):
- Sigillography, the study of seals.
- Chronology, the study of timekeeping.
- Codicology, the study of handwritten books.
- Papyrology, the study of papyrus texts.
- Epigraphy, the study of inscriptions.
- Heraldry, the study of coats of arms.
- Numismatics, the study of coinage.
- Linguistics, the study of language.
- Genealogy, the study of family relationships.
- Prosopography, the study of names and careers, or the use
of biographical data to construct group portraits.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 60:
Sources must be evaluated not only in terms of those external
characteristics on which we have been focusing, the questions of where, when,
and by whom a source was created and whether it is "genuine" or not.
Traditionally, they have also been evaluated in terms of what historians
have thought of as internal criteria.
Howell and Prevenier now list the chief elements of source criticism:
- The genealogy of the document (pages 61-62), whether it is the original,
a copy, or a copy of a copy.
- The genesis of the document (pages 62-63), the circumstances, authority,
and events in or under which it was produced.
- The originality of the document (pages 63-64), whether it
is innovating or merely passing on already current information.
- The interpretation of the document (pages 64-65), the extraction of
some kind of meaning from it.
- The authorial authority of the document (pages 65-66), the relation
of its author to the subject matter, whether eyewitness, earwitness, or
even further removed.
- The competence of the observer (pages 66-68); is the author qualified
to report and capable of reporting critically and with comprehension?
- The trustworthiness of the observer (page 68); is the author lying
or telling what he or she believes is the truth?
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, pages 69-71, on comparisons of sources
(which section covers pages 69-79):
Typically, historians do not rely on just one source to
study an event or a historical process, but on many, and they construct
their own interpretations about the past by means of comparison among
sources—by sifting information contained in many sources, by listening
to many voices. ....
The essential problem here is distinguishing among the useful,
less useful, and useless sources. Generally, historians consider sources to
be useless (for reporting purposes) if they derive from other, usually older,
sources. Although it is sometimes hard to decide if a source is in some way
derived from another, once that assessment is made, eliminating the dependent
source is usually easy. It is much harder, however, to rank sources that all
seem to be "original" in that each provides an independent account of the
particular events in question.
Nineteenth-century historians developed systematic rules for making such
comparisons. Two of the best-known rule books of the age, that of E. Bernheim,
published in 1889 (Lehrbuch der historischen Methode und der
Geschichtsphilosophie [Guidebook for Historical Method and the
Philosophy of History]), and Charles Langlois and Charles Seignobos,
from 1898 (Introduction aux études historiques [Introduction to
the Study of History]), provide a seven-step process, which we have
summarized below. As we shall see, the procedure hardly guarantees the kind
of scientific proof these scholars and their contemporaries imagined as
the historians' goal (only numbers (2) and (6) seem uncontroversial),
but it can, nevertheless, provide entry into the challenging world of
source comparison.
This sevenfold list Howell and Prevenier give as follows:
- If the sources all agree about an event, historians can consider the
event proved.
- However, majority does not rule; even if most sources relate events in
one way, that version will not prevail unless it passes the tests of critical
textual analysis....
- The source whose account can be confirmed by reference to outside
authorities in some of its parts can be trusted in its entirety if it is
impossible similarly to confirm the entire text.
- When two sources disagree on a particular point, the historian will prefer
the souce with the most "authority"—i.e., the source created by the
expert or the eyewitness....
- Eyewitnesses are, in general, to be preferred, especially in circumstances
where the ordinary observer could have accurately reported what transpired and,
more specifically, when they deal with facts known by most contemporaries.
- If two independently created sources agree on a matter, the reliability
of each is measurably enhanced.
- When two sources disagree (and there is no other means of evaluation),
then historians take the source which seems to accord best with common sense.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, pages 74-75, after using an argument from silence
in an example involving Israeli involvement in the 1982 attack
on refugee camps in Beirut:
Of course, an argument from silence can serve as
presumptive evidence of the "silenced" event only if, as in this
case, the person suppressing the information was in a position
to have the information, and was purposing to give a full
account of the story from which he omitted the crucial
information, and if there were no compelling reasons why
he should have omitted the information (other than the wish
to conceal). ....
Another difficulty with an "argument from silence" is that
historians cannot assume—as nineteenth-century scholars
such as Seignobos would have assumed—that an observer
of a particular "fact" would have automatically recorded
the fact. .... In addition, it is clear, silences can be
inadvertently created when texts are partly obliterated, lost,
or changed in unexpected ways. And, conversely, it is naive
to assume that everything that a text reports was actually
observed—much less that it occurred!
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 75:
Although historians must often reason from
silences, they more commonly reason from positive evidence,
and in their accounts they employ a number of logical processes.
Very often historians reason by interpolation or by analogy,
as though inserting missing pieces in a puzzle whose overall
pattern they can discern by comparison with other, analogous
situations. ....
Comparison of this kind can be a useful technique, but it
is also a treacherous one. Comparisons are never perfect.
Historical actors are creative; they learn from former
events.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 76:
Reasoning by analogy, although useful and often
necessary, is thus often inadequate. Hence, historians employ
other kinds of logical processes as well, often turning to what
is labeled "the scientific method." In these instances, historians
construct testable hypotheses and marshal evidence to test them,
following the principles of the physical sciences. Claude
Bernard, a nineteenth-century positivist scientist, was one of
the first, in 1865, to lay out these steps systematically:
(1) observation, (2) hypothesis, (3) fit between the hypothesis
and the given facts, (4) verification of the hypothesis with
new facts. For historians who would follow this method,
"observation" consists of critical analysis of the sources
using the methods we have considered in chapter 2 [on pages
43-68, entitled Technical Analysis of Sources]. The
"hypothesis" is an effort at explanation—an attempt
to make causal connections between the observed "facts." The
process is dialectic, so that the resultant hypothesis is then
tested by new facts, revised if necessary, and retested.
And so on.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 77:
Although it is a simple process to think up
hypotheses, it is no simple task to formulate hypotheses that
actually link the observed pieces of evidence—that
can explain the facts available, not those that the scholar
might wish to have. Often, it takes many tries before the
scholar can formulate a hypothesis that really works—one
that satisfactorily accounts for the known evidence. There is
no formula for success in this difficult
venture.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 78:
The difficulties of applying the so-called
scientific method to historical research means that historians
must often satisfy themselves with rules of logic that appear
less watertight, making statements that seem probable, not
"proved" in any "scientific" sense.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 80, on establishing evidentiary
satisfaction (which section covers pages 79-84):
To a large extent, the amount or quality of
evidence required depends on the kind of event being
studied.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 81:
But historians never have just what they want
or need. At one extreme is the historian limited to one
source. Einhard's Life of Charlemagne is, for example,
the only source scholars have about the private life of
Europe's first emperor. Like many of the political biographies
written today, this one is more hagiography than critical
biography, and in the best of worlds historians might well
refuse to use it as evidence about Charlemagne's life and
his character. But historians, although conscious that they
are prisoners of the unique source and bear all the risks
that this involves, use it because it is all they have.
At the other extreme are historians studying the recent
past. They have a great many sources, and in many ways their
problems are thus fewer. But even here there is no
certainty.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 84, on the facts that matter
(which section covers pages 84-87):
[T]he status of any "fact" available to the
historian is always insecure. Nevertheless, however
self-conscious they are about the limits of their knowledge,
about its particularity..., historians must construct their
interpretations about the past out of information that
they deem to be of factlike status—information that
is available to them for the purposes of their
inquiry.
Martha Howell and Walter Prevenier, From
Reliable Sources, page 84:
Often, historians will privilege evidence that
seems to point to a recurring picture, to add to a story that
seems familiar or repetitive. Always, however, this is a
risky choice. In some sense, all events are unique, and every
fact about an event is unique. ....
This is not to say, however, that there are not patterns
in history, similarities of circumstance that allow the
historian fruitfully to compare one place and time with
another, to look for patterns of recurrence and thus
patterns of causality. Only when one considers how similar
people behave in similar situations can one begin to make
generalizations about the relationships between events that
we call cause and effect. Only then does history become
more than the banal repetition of events.
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, pages 115-117:
The historian often has to depend upon
secondary works (i.e., other historians' second-hand
narratives and expositions) for his knowledge of the
background into which to fit the contemporary documents,
but he frequently also finds that, just as a good secondary
account will enable him better to understand a contemporary
document, so the correct understanding of the contemporary
document will enable him to correct the secondary account.
In the end, his knowledge is best tested by a critical
analysis of the testimony of contemporaries.
Hence, as a general rule, the careful historian will be
suspicious of secondary works in history, even the best ones.
He should use them only for four purposes: (1) to derive the
setting into which to fit the contemporary evidence upon
his problem, being always prepared, however, to doubt and
to rectify the secondary account wherever a critical analysis
of contemporary witnesses makes it necessary to do so;
(2) to get leads to other bibliographical data; (3) to
acquire quotations or citations from contemporary or other
sources, but only if they are not more fully available
elsewhere and always with skepticism about their accuracy,
especially if they are translated from another tongue; and
(4) to derive interpretations of and hypotheses regarding his
problem, but only with a view to testing or improving upon
them, never with the intention of accepting them
outright.
In general, the rule regarding time-lapse as applied to
secondary sources is the reverse of that rule as applied
to primary sources. The further away secondary sources are
in time from the events of which they tell, the more reliable
they are likely to be. That is true not only because
impartiality and detachment are easier for remote periods of
history, but also because as time elapses, more materials
are likely to become available. In addition, the last writer
has the help of the materials and interpretations contained
in the earlier studies of his subject. Unfortunately, later
historians are not always as competent as earlier ones. All
too frequently they are just hack-writers, content merely
with "re-hashing" the earlier works without presenting new
evidence or points of view.
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, pages 90-91:
Four general rules will suffice here to
indicate why one group of documents may be given precedence
over another. (1) As we have seen, incomplete observation
and faulty memory are often responsible for the inadequacy
of testimony. Because a witness's reliability is, in general,
inversely proportional to the time-lapse between
the observation of the event and the witness's recollection,
the closer the time of making a document was to the event
it records, the better it is likely to be for historical
purposes. (2) Some documents were originally intended purely
as records or aids to one's memory, some as reports to other
persons, some as apologia, some as propaganda, and so on.
Because documents differ in this way in purpose, the
more serious the author's intention to make a mere record,
the more dependable his document as a historical source.
(3) Because the effort, on the one hand, to palliate the
truth or, on the other, to decorate it with literary,
rhetorical, or dramatic flourishes tends to increase as
the expected audience increases, in general the fewer the
number for whose eyes the document was meant (i.e., the
greater its confidential nature), the more "naked"
its contents are likely to be. (4) Because the testimony
of a schooled or experienced observer and reporter (e.g.,
a professional soldier reporting a battle, an experienced
correspondent describing an interview, a veteran policeman
reporting an accident, etc.) is generally superior to that
of the untrained and casual observer and reporter, the
greater the expertness of the author in the matter
he is reporting, the more reliable his report.
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, pages 100-101:
The historian or psychologist interested
in the inner springs of consciousness may, however, sometimes
find the idealized personality of an autobiography more
meaningful than the more realistic character revealed by
better sources. It is also true that for the correct
understanding of personal influences, cults, and legends,
the idealization by disciples often is a more meaningful
historical fact than the actual personality (see Chapter
XI).
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, pages 139-140:
In the process of analysis the historian
should constantly keep in mind the relevant particulars
within the document rather than the document as a whole.
Regarding each particular he asks: Is it credible? It might
be well to point out again that what is meant by calling
a particular credible is not that it is actually
what happened, but that it is as close to what
actually happened as we can learn from a critical examination
of the best available sources. This means
verisimilar at a high level. It connotes something more
than merely not being preposterous in itself or even
than plausible and yet is short of meaning
accurately descriptive of past actuality. In other
words, the historian establishes verisimilitude
rather than objective truth. ....
A historical "fact" thus may be defined as a particular
derived directly or indirectly from historical documents
and regarded as credible after careful testing in accordance
with the canons of historical method (see below, p. 150).
An infinity and a multiple variety of facts of this kind
are accepted by all historians: e.g., that Socrates really
existed; that Alexander invaded India; that the Romans
built the Pantheon....
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, pages 143-144:
Having accumulated his notes, the investigator
must now separate the credible from the incredible. ....
In detailed investigations few documents are significant
as a whole; they serve most often only as mines from which
to extract historical ore. Each bit of ore, however, may
contain flaws of its own. The general reliability of an
author, in other words, has significance only as establishing
the probably credibility of his particular statements. From
that process of scupulous analysis emerges an important
general rule: for each particular of a document the
process of establishing credibility should be separately
undertaken regardless of the general credibility of the
author.
As has already been pointed out (p. 138), some
identification of the author is necessary to test a document's
authenticity. In the subsequent process of determining the
credibility of its particulars, even the most genuine
of documents should be regarded as guilty of deceipt until
proven innocent. ....
The historian, however, is frequently obliged to use
documents written by persons about whom nothing or relatively
little is known. Even the hundreds of biographical
dictionaries and encyclopedias already in existence may be
of no help because the author's name is unknown or, if
known, not to be found in the reference works. The historian
must therefore depend upon the document itself to teach
him what it can about the author. A single brief document
may teach him much if he asks the right
questions.
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, page 147:
It would be relatively easy, even if the
Gettysburg Address were a totally strange document, to
establish its approximate date. It was obviously composed
"four-score and seven years" after the Declaration of
Independence, hence in 1863. But few strange documents
are so easily dated. One has frequently to resort to the
conjectures known to the historian as the terminus
non ante quem ("the point not before which") and the
terminus non post quem ("the point not after which").
These termini, or points, have to be established
by internal evidence — by clues given within the
document itself.
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, page 149:
In a law court it is frequently assumed that
all testimony of a witness, though under oath, is suspect
if the opposing lawyers can impugn his general character
or by examination and cross-examination create doubt of
his veracity in some regard. Even in modern law courts
the old maxim falsus in uno, falsus in omnibus tends
to be overemphasized. In addition, hearsay evidence is as a
general rule excluded; certain kinds of witnesses are
"privileged" or "unqualified" and therefore are not obliged
to testify or are kept from testifying....
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, page 150:
The historian, however, is prosecutor,
attorney for the defense, judge, and jury all in one. But as
judge he rules out no evidence whatever if it is relevant.
To him any single detail of testimony is credible —
even if it is contained in a document obtained by force or
fraud, or is otherwise impeachable, or is based on hearsay
evidence, or is from an interested witness — provided
it can pass four tests:
(1) Was the ultimate source of the detail (the primary
witness) able to tell the truth?
(2) Was the primary witness willing to tell the
truth?
(3) Is the primary witness accurately reported
with regard to the detail under examination?
(4) Is there any independent corroboration of
the detail under examination?
Any detail (regardless of what the source or who the
author) that passes all four tests is credible
historical evidence. It will bear repetition that the
primary witness and the detail are now the
subjects of examination, not the source as a
whole.
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, pages 188-189:
A large part of historical composition is
argumentative. It attempts to answer questions such as "Why
did Caesar cross the Rubicon?" or "Did Washington understand
the terms of his capitulation at Fort Necessity?" or "Did
Nasser really believe that American and English airplanes
aided the Israeli Army in 1967?" The argument in such
cases usually consists of a mustering of the evidence on one
and the other side and of a conclusion either that one side
seems more plausible than the other or that, neither side of
the argument being wholly convincing, the historian has to
suspend judgment. In such cases the historian is dealing with
evidence as concrete things as well as abstract thought;
the evidence he is dealing with, whether words or artifacts
or whatever, still exists — a record of recollection
by Caesar, a capitulation signed by Washington, a transcription
of an intercepted telephone conversation with Nasser, and the
like — even if only in a translated and re-edited version
rather than as the original document itself. When presenting
his argument in cases like these, the historian therefore is
dealing with evidence that is still extant in some form,
good or bad, and he is likely to speak of it in the present
tense: "Caesar's Commentaries say..."; "Washington's
signature is..."; "Nasser's voice sounds...." Such a use
of present tenses is not only permissible; it may well be
the best way to use them.
Louis Gottschalk, Understanding
History, page 163:
Even when the fact in question may not be well-known,
certain kinds of statements are both incidental and probable
to such a degree that error or falsehood seems unlikely. If an ancient
inscription on a road tells us that a certain proconsul built that
road while Augustus was princeps, it may be doubted without further
corroboration that that proconsul really built the road, but would
be harder to doubt that the road was built during the principate of
Augustus. If an advertisement informs readers that "A and B Coffee
may be bought at any reliable grocer's at the unusual price of fifty
cents a pound," all the inferences of the advertisement may well be
doubted without corroboration except that there is a brand of coffee
on the market called "A and B Coffee."
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 304:
Proof by circumstances (indirect,
presumptive, circumstantial evidence), as differentiated
from proof by testimony (testimonial evidence), is used
to establish the reality of an alleged fact, or to render
a doubtful fact certain. Very often circumstances or
indications of varying number and significance for each
particular case point to one and the same conclusion.
Taken individually, they yield as a rule only probability;
taken collectively, they issue in certainty when their
concurrence is such that it cannot be explained except
by the reality of the alleged fact or facts to which
they point.
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 305:
Cumulative or converging evidence is
virtually circumstantial. It is "a heaping up" (L.
cumulus) of bits of evidence, individually never
more than probable, and often only slightly so, until
they form a mass of evidence, the net result of which
is certainty. But, as already noted, the resulting
certainty does not issue directly from the mass or
cumulus of probabilities, since no number of mere
probabilities added together can logically produce
certainty. To produce such effect, one must invoke the
"principle of sufficient reason," by arguing that the
only possible explanation why so many bits of evidence
point to the same alleged fact, is that the fact is
objectively true.
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 260:
For the reliability of the popular tradition
of a historical fact, certain conditions must be fulfilled.
(a) Broad conditions: (1) Unbroken
series of witnesses; (2) several parallel and
independent series of witnesses.
(b) Particular conditions: (1) Content
a public event of importance; (2) general belief for
a definite period; (3) absence of protest during that
period; (4) relatively limited duration; (5)
influence of the critical spirit, and application of critical
investigation; (6) absence of denial by the critically
minded.
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 273:
Lanzoni [in Genesi], following De Smedt,
distinguishes two types of legend, mere legends, and
historical legends. The former have no direct or
explicit historical content whatever; the latter have content
of this kind in varying degree. Both types can be of use
to the historian by preserving data of value, whether
implicitly or explicitly. The legend itself may be pure
fiction, and at the same time incidentally (or, as the
philosophers say, praeter intentionem) may picture
vividly and even accurately various phases of a vanished
culture or civilization.
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, pages 143-144:
Analogy argues from the resemblance of two
things in one or more respects to their necessary or supposedly
necessary resemblance also in other respects. The basis of an
argument of this kind is the double principle that every
being shows certain attributes or traits corresponding
to its nature, that every efficient cause has a corresponding
effect; consequently, similar beings show similar attributes
or traits, while similar causes have similar effects, and
vice versa. Historical analogy applies the principle
of analogy to historical data as a method of logical
proof.
Garraghan goes on to list a few kinds of faulty analogy,
one of which is, on page 145, the interpretation of ancient
texts according to contemporary ideas and customs. Surely
a good caveat to keep in mind when constructing an
argument from analogy.
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 146:
History is concerned immediately with single,
individual facts; mediately with such generalized truths as
can be derived from the individual facts. Generalizations in
history may be applicable only to the past, or they may
be of universal application, and as such, independent of time
and place. Examples of the two types are respectively the
statements, "the Athenians were an art-loving people"; "a
strongly centralized government is the best in war time." It is
only in the case of the latter type that we can speak with
consistency of "historical laws." The logical process
employed in arriving at either kind of generalization is
known as induction or, more specifically, incomplete
induction, which may be defined as "the legitimate
derivation of general laws or truths from a limited number
of individual cases."
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 151:
As a method of investigation in history,
the use of statistics may be taken to mean the collection,
tabulation, and analysis of numerical facts of a given
category, with a view to deducing therefrom averages,
proportions, and other uniformities or laws, useful to
the historian.
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 153:
An intelligent use of hypothesis conditions
all progress in scientific research. As a rule it is only by
thinking out various likely explanations of a phenomenon,
by testing them one after the other, and rejecting such as
are unsatisfactory, that the true explanation is finally
brought to light. This is the course pursued by the physicist
and other specialists in the natural sciences; it is a necessary
procedure in the social sciences as well. Historical hypothesis
may be applied not merely to the data supplied from sources,
but to the sources themselves in the whole range of problems
which they present, such as authorship, textual integrity,
interpretation, trustworthiness.
Garraghan necessarily reminds the reader on page 154 that
certain dangers attend argumentation by hypothesis, chief among
which is the fitting of facts into the hypothesis rather than
the fitting of the hypothesis into the facts.
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 160:
Conjecture does not greatly differ from
hypothesis. Both terms are often used as synonyms in every day
speech; technically, however, they differ in meaning. Conjecture
generally regards individual facts or phenomena, while hypothesis,
being of wider range and significance, deals typically with
bodies of facts, general situations.
Garraghan now divides conjecture into three kinds. The first
is conjectural emendation of a text; the second is conjectural
restoration of longer passages of a text or even entire
documents; the third is conjectural detail, used to fill out the
background of a text.
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 162:
The argument from silence aims to prove the
non-reality of an alleged fact from the circumstance that
contemporary or later sources of information fail to say
anything about it. It is sometimes misleadingly called the
negative argument; but this can easily be taken to mean
something false, namely, that the argument rests on an
explicit denial of some fact.
Garraghan offers only two conditions that an argument
from silence must fulfill. First, that the writer whose silence
is invoked would have certainly been in a position to know
about the alleged fact; second, that the writer would have
certainly made mention of it under the circumstances.
Gilbert J. Garraghan, A
Guide to Historical Method, page 166:
The argument a priori is based on antecedent
probability or improbability. Direct evidence may be lacking
that a man is guilty of a crime imputed to him; but his known
character, antecedents, habits, make it likely or unlikely that
he is guilty. Here the reasoning concerns facts or circumstances
prior in time to the occurrence of the event in
question.
|